Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

download Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

of 40

Transcript of Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    1/40

     

    Analogy and Falsification in Descartes’ Physics

    Gideon Manning, Caltech

    Abstract 

    In this paper I address Descartes’ use of analogy in physics. First, I introduce Descartes’

    hypothetical reasoning, distinguishing between analogy and hypothesis. Second, I examine in

    detail Descartes’ use of analogy to both discover causes and add plausibility to his hypotheses –

    even though not always explicitly stated, Descartes’ practice assumes a unified view of the

    subject matter of physics as the extension of bodies in terms of their size, shape and the motion

    of their parts. Third, I present Descartes’ unique “philosophy of analogy,” where the absence of

    analogy serves as a criterion for falsifying proposed explanations in physics. I conclude by

    defending Descartes’ philosophy of analogy by appeal to the value scientists assign to simplicity

    in their explanations.

    Keywords

    René Descartes; analogy; hypothesis, falsification, explanation

    I. Introduction

    The reception of Descartes’ physics could be described through the various rejections of his

    many analogies. Take, as an example, his account of magnetism. Descartes claims in the

    Principles that invisible particles traveling from a magnet’s two poles likely have a shape and

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    2/40

    twisting motion similar to that of a screw (Descartes 1996, VIII 275ff.).1 He reasons that when

     particles emanating from a magnet come into contact with objects they can, depending on their

    orientation and motion, pull objects toward a magnet or push them away. Although Descartes is

    citing a common effect in his explanation of magnetism – screws push and pull objects and so do

    magnets – this analogy, and the evidence Descartes believes it provides about causes in the

    subvisible world, hardly satisfied the majority of his contemporaries. Later in the century even

    the one time Cartesian Christiaan Huygens describes the Principles as a “Romance” filled with

    “chimeras” where “conjectures [serve] as truths, which can be seen in the grooved particles that

    [Descartes] employs in the explanation of the magnet” (Huygen 1988-1950, X 405).

    2

     

    My aim in this paper is to elucidate the role of analogies in Descartes’ physics. In doing

    so I hope to show that Descartes’ use of analogy is more defensible – i.e. less a chimera or mere 

    conjecture – than is usually thought; it is part of Descartes’ effort to “submit [his] reasons to

    examination by the senses” (1996, II 366). More than this, I will suggest that Descartes’ theory

    of falsification holds considerable appeal if we substitute the ideal of simplicity among

    explanations for his metaphysical commitment to matter being nothing but extension. I begin in

    the second section by noting the difference between analogies – comparaisons in French,

    comparationes in Latin – and hypotheses – hypothèses and suppositions in French, hypotheses,

     positiones and suppositiones in Latin. In the third section I present Descartes’ famous analogies

    1 When offering my own translation, I cite the original language text in Descartes 1996,

    including volume in Roman numerals, followed by page number.

    2 For similar seventeenth century responses to Descartes’ physics, see the references in Anstey

    (2005). A fairly recent historian, Larry Laudan, accuses Descartes of resorting to claims

    supported “with neither empirical evidence nor a priori reasons” (1966, p. 79).

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    3/40

    from the Dioptrics. As Descartes’ scientific practice shows, the primary purpose of analogy is to

    aid in the discovery of causes and to illustrate how subvisible mechanisms might produce known

    effects. In either case, analogies utilize what we know of the sensible world. What drives

    Descartes’ search for subvisible mechanisms is the hypothesis and erstwhile metaphysical truth

    that the natural world is nothing more than extended matter. In the fourth section I consider

    Descartes’ remarks about analogy in response to criticism of the Dioptrics. Building upon

    section three, I reconstruct Descartes’ defense of his use of analogy and show that his

     provocative claim, “when someone makes an assertion concerning nature which cannot be

    explained by any... analogy, I think I have demonstrative knowledge that the point is false,”

    depends on his unified view of matter as extension (1991, 122). I conclude by showing that our

    own interest in simplicity when forced to choose among competing explanations can be used to

    support Descartes’ “philosophy of analogy”.

    II. Hypothesis vs. Analogy

    There are now several competing accounts of the proper role of analogy in science but, however

    one defines analogical reasoning, a good analogy indicates that a certain phenomenon or process

    is similar to a better-known phenomenon or process in one or more non-trivial ways.3 Descartes’

    overwhelming interest when using analogies lies in identifying similar effects and then inferring

    the existence of a similar cause between the phenomena or processes he is comparing.

    Schematically then, all Descartes’ analogies appear in the following ratio-like form:

    Known Effect1 : Known Cause :: Known Effect2 : Unknown Cause.

    3 Hesse (1966) remains the classic treatment of analogy in science but Bartha (2010) represents a

    new benchmark for the subject.

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    4/40

     

    The better known phenomenon (Known Effect1 : Known Cause) is almost invariably a

    mechanical contrivance for Descartes, and the cause being sought (Unknown Cause) is immune

    to direct observation because of its small size or remote location. To use Descartes’ magnetism

    example again, a screw with its pulling and pushing action can be observed and understood by

    anyone. By contrast, the subvisible mechanisms responsible for the pulling and pushing action of

    a magnet are not well understood and are immune to direct observation. The Known Effect1 is

    the screw’s pushing and pulling action and the Known Cause is the orientation of the screw’s

    threads and its motion. Known Effect2 is the pushing and pulling action of a magnet. Thus, the

    effects in the two cases are similar and observable. On the basis of this similarity, Descartes

     presents an analogy between the screw and the magnet and concludes that the Unknown Cause –

    the cause of the magnet’s properties – might be particles that are similar to a screw in their shape

    and motion.4 

    From our contemporary perspective, one of the most distinctive features of Descartes’

    analogies is his preference to avoid referring to them as “analogies”.5 In fact, though for the sake

    4 For the Principles, Descartes commissioned illustrations depicting magnets expelling

    subvisible screw-like particles (1996, VIII 288). The connection among these illustrations,

    imagination, vision and conjecture more generally is discussed in Luthy (2006) and Bellis

    (2010). Both works show that Descartes’ views develop and change over time.

    5 Although Descartes’ magnetism analogy is innovative, many his analogies are quite pedestrian.

    Such is the case with his analogy between lightning and fire (Descartes, 1996, VI 317; Martin,

    2011), his analogy between vision and the tactile sensations caused by a blind man’s stick

    (Descartes 1996, VI 84; Sabra 1967, p. 55), and his analogy between the motion of a celestial

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    5/40

    of convenience I will continue to refer to “Descartes’ analogies”, as far as I am aware Descartes

    uses the French “analogie” on only six occasions in all of his writing (e.g., 1996, XI 158). He

    uses the Latin “analogia” to contrast what he is trying to do with what his contemporaries often

    do, as in “nor should it be thought that this is said merely by way of analogy [ per analogiam]”

    (Ibid., X 412; Cf. Ibid., V 270).6 The analogies from the Dioptrics are “comparisons

    [comparaisons]” and those from the Meteors are instances of reasoning by “example and

    similarity [exemplum & similitudinem]” (Ibid., VI 83 and I 422, respectively).7 In the Principles, 

    analogies are typically “comparisons [comparationes]” or efforts to “compare

    [consero/comparo]” (e.g., Ibid., VIII 87 and 110, respectively). In Proposition 8 from the Rules

     body and a boat’s movement in a river (Descartes, 1996, XI 57-58; Palmerino, 2007). Notice

    though that in all these cases Descartes is using similar effects to infer a similar cause.

    6 Descartes’ biased use of “analogia” is noted in Galison (1984). At the urging of an anonymous

    referee I have consulted the ARTFL database and discovered that “analogie” appears rarely in

    French texts of the seventeenth century. Comparing it with “comparaison,” which is Descartes

     preferred term for what we think of as his analogies, “analogie” is roughly one tenth as common.

    To this extent, Descartes’ preference for “comparaison” is consistent with the preferences of his

    contemporaries. For more on the ancestry of Descartes’ different terminology in connection with

    “analogy”, see note 20. 

    7 The Meteors is a complicated case because Descartes’ initial analogies from this work are

     presented as “suppositions” but, as I just indicated, they are later classed with his other

    comparaisons (1996, VI 233). The analogy between a raindrop and a prism in the Meteros,

    which serves in the experimental and quantitative success of the account of the rainbow,

    Descartes calls a comparaison (Ibid., VI 329).

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    6/40

     for the direction of the mind , Descartes does not advise us to seek “analogies” when trying to

    discover the nature of light but to “enumerate all the other natural powers so that, by means of

    knowledge of some other one, [we] might come to understand this one, at least by imitation

    [imitationem]” (Ibid, X 395).8 

     Nevertheless, the presence of what we easily recognize as analogical reasoning in

    Descartes’ scientific work at every stage in his development, and the emergence of a stable

    terminology (comparaison/comparatio) in his writing beginning in the 1630s, suggest that

    analogies are an integral part of Descartes’ method in physics. There is no shortage of discussion

    about Descartes’ scientific method, and there are many valuable studies of the evolving use of

    hypotheses and expérience by Descartes and subsequent Cartesians (Laudan 1966; Garber 1978;

    Hatfield 1988; McMullin 2008, 2009; Clarke 1982, 1989, 2010; Ariew 2010). What is generally

    missing from these studies, however, is focused attention on Descartes’ use of analogy as distinct

    from, or as a special case of, his use of hypotheses (Cf. Statile 1999; Cf. Garber [Unpublished]).

    To rectify this situation and in order to provide what I hope will be a more complete account of

    Descartes’ method in physics, I will spend the rest of this section discussing Descartes’ use of

    hypothesis in order to prepare us for a closer look at his analogies in later sections.

    Starting in the 1620s, with the Rules, Descartes appeals to “suppositiones”, i.e.

    hypotheses. In this early work he likens his method to the one “in geometry when you make

    certain suppositions about quantity, which in no way weaken the force of the demonstrations,

    8 Descartes’ use of imitatio here is unusual. The term comes from the rhetorical tradition and is

    usually reserved for the imitation of a style or manner. Descartes uses the French derivative of

    imitatio – imiter  – when he claims to imitate the method of the astronomer in the  Diotrics (1996,

    VI, 83).

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    7/40

    even though in physics you often take a different view of the nature of quantity” (1985, 40,

    modified). Just as the geometer assumes certain principles, so Descartes assumes certain

     principles for the sake of his demonstrations. In later years, Descartes compares his use of

    hypotheses to the astronomers’, “whose suppositions are almost all false or uncertain, but who

    nevertheless draw many very true and certain consequences from them because they are related

    to various observations they have made” (Ibid., 152-53, modified). This comparison from the

     Dioptrics is more suggestive than the earlier one from the Rules because Descartes find a place

    for “false and uncertain” principles as well as observations, the latter being, as we will see,

    where analogies enter into his method. Holding this point for later discussion, collectively the

    comparisons to geometry and astronomy tell us that Descartes’ hypotheses may be false

     principles or, because his method is a method of physics, the wrong causes for the effects that

    they are introduced to explain. Still, what matters is that the “conclusions” or “consequences”

    follow from the hypotheses.

     Notice that just as one could assume for the sake of argument a principle or cause that

    may be false, one could also assume for the sake of argument a principle or cause known to be

    true. In spite of what Descartes writes in the passages above, and what the comparison to

    astronomy might suggest, it is not true that all of Descartes’ hypotheses are potentially “false or

    uncertain”. First, in some cases Descartes vindicates in his metaphysics what he otherwise

    labeles as “hypotheses”. These hypotheses are not potentially false or uncertain, however, they

    are metaphysical or “absolute certainties”. Second, Descartes’ standards for knowledge or

    “demonstration” in physics appear to evolve throughout the 1630s. Without appealing to

    metaphysics, in some places he maintains that his hypotheses are not potentially “false and

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    8/40

    uncertain” but rather the only ones that can be found that both explain the effects while

    maximizing separate epistemic values.

    Before elaborating on these two points, I want to mark the important distinction between

    hypotheses that are also metaphysical truths and those that are never metaphysical truths.

    Henceforth I will discriminate between:

    Stage 1 hypotheses: principles or causes that have an a priori metaphysical justification

    although they sometimes appear in Descartes’ physics as hypotheses.

    Stage 2 hypotheses: principles or causes that appear in Descartes’ physics without ever

    having an a priori metaphysical justification.

    Stage 1 hypotheses come first in Descartes’ order of exposition and they serve more as

    theoretical constraints on explanation than as literal efficient causes. There are, as we will see,

    many instances in which Descartes claims he can “deduce” all of his hypotheses from a

    metaphysical foundation, but he nowhere suggests that this eliminates the category of Stage 2

    hypotheses.9  From the standpoint of Descartes’ physics, as Clarke (1990) emphasizes, the most

    important point to remember is that both Stage 1 and Stage 2 hypotheses serve as principles for

    deducing effects from causes. In other words, whether conjectures, known falsehoods or

    9 The scholastic distinction between general as opposed to specific or particular physics is

    another way to understand this point. Stage 1 hypotheses enter in the context of Descartes’

    general physics but Stage 2 hypotheses never do.

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    9/40

    metaphysical truths, the primary role of these hypotheses is to account for effects in the natural

    world that the physicist takes as given and in need of causal explanation.

    In order to further clarify the difference between a Stage 1 and a Stage 2 hypothesis, take

    as an example the Stage 1 hypothesis that matter is just extension . In The World , Descartes

    writes of planning to “expressly suppose [supposons expressément ] that it [matter] does not have

    the form of earth, fire, or air, or any other more specific form, like that of wood, stone or metal”.

    He adds, continuing his supposition, “this matter may be divided into as many parts having as

    many shapes as we can imagine, and ... each of its parts is capable of taking on as many motions

    as we can conceive” (Ibid., 91). A decade later, in the Principles, it is one of Descartes’

    certainties deriving from Part One’s metaphysical preface that “all the bodies of the universe are

    composed of one and the same matter, which is divisible into indefinitely many parts” (Ibid.,

    256). What was once a hypothesis has been converted into a metaphysical certainty.10

     

    More to the point for our discussion, when Descartes offers Stage 1 and Stage 2

    hypotheses in his physics they look to be mere conjectures or ad hoc assumptions whenever an

    10 In spite of this shift from the The World  to the Principles, what follows the Stage 1 hypothesis

    that matter is extension in both works are a series of Stage 2 hypotheses. First come suppositions

    [supposons / suppositionum] related to how God initially divides up matter and introduces

    motion into its many parts and then comes a hypothetical matter theory with three discrete

    elements: fire, air and earth. After this, Descartes conjoins his laws of nature, which are not

    hypotheses to his suppositions about initial states and to his matter theory. From this

    combination of principles he infers the most general features of the world: planets, stars, comets,

    etc. A great deal of criticism has been directed at these inferences, but Descartes deserves credit

    for his commitment to a naturalized and developmental account of the natural world.

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    10/40

    analogy is not instrumental in their discovery. A good example of this is Descartes’ Stage 2

    hypothesis from the Principles that the world was created in an initial state of “proportion or

    order [ proportio vel ordo]” (Ibid., 257).11

     This claim is not supported by evidence of any kind

    except (arguably) the fact that God has the power to do everything that we can conceive. Such a

    constraint hardly curtails Descartes’ prodigious imagination, however, and in the Principles he

    acknowledges that we are licensed “to make any assumption [assumere]” about the initial state

    of matter because “we cannot determine by reason alone how big these pieces of matter are, or

    how fast they move, or what kinds of circle they describe” (Ibid., 256). God, quite simply “might

    have instituted” what Descartes describes as “countless different configurations” of matter

    ultimately producing the effects we now observe. While he does offer the “sole proviso that all

    the consequences of our assumption must agree with experience”, this is not to say that

    observational evidence led to the discovery of the hypothesis or that his Stage 2 hypotheses are

    true (Ibid., 256-257). Rather, the hypotheses must allow us to save the phenomena – i.e. to

    explain all known effects – and, failing this confirmation, the hypotheses can be rejected.12

     

    11 This is an initial state the complete opposite of the one Descartes hypothesizes in The World ,

    which was one of chaos entirely lacking “order or proportion [ordre ni proportion]” (Descartes,

    1985, p. 91).

    12 Descartes sometimes explains away experiences inconsistent with the consequences of his

    hypotheses by citing the complex interactions between bodies that alter the expected effect (e.g.,

    1996, VIII 70; for discussion see Sakelleriadis 1982). More generally we can say that Descartes

    refuses to give up his hypotheses until an equally all encompassing hypothesis or group of

    hypotheses can be found.

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    11/40

      This brings into sharp relief the second reason that Descartes’ suppositions are not

     potentially “false and uncertain”, for in spite of passages like the one cited in the last paragraph

    about “countless configurations”, Descartes will often claim that his Stage 2 hypotheses could

    not be false. The literature criticizing Descartes here is vast.13

     As we just saw, Descartes

    acknowledges that God could have created matter in any number of initial states. This implies

    more than one Stage 2 hypothesis can be used to save the phenomena and, generalizing, it means

    that no single Stage 2 hypothesis can be judged true and certain.14

     But Descartes adds in the

    Principles that he does “not consider it possible to invent  [non puto... posse excogitari] any other

     principles that are simpler, or more intelligible, or indeed more probable [ probabiliora]” than the

    ones he offers (1996, VIII 102, emphasis added). These further standards for assessing

    competing hypotheses – simplicity, intelligibility and probability – go beyond merely saving the

     phenomena or agreeing with experience. Applying them, Descartes seems to believe that all his

    hypotheses must be correct.

    Later in the Principles, Descartes elaborates on this thought with more technical

    terminology. He acknowledges that his method has provided only “moral certainties” consistent

    with God’s goodness. But still, Descartes intimates that his method has led to “absolute

    certainties.” As he writes:

    13 Descartes’ vacillation on the status of his hypotheses is the subject of McMullin 2008 and

    2009, which include extensive bibliographies.

    14 One can discern this point from Descartes’ account of the competing hypotheses about the

    Earth’s motion as well (1996, VIII 84-86; see also an earlier remark in defense of the Discourse

    in Ibid., II 200).

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    12/40

    there are some matters even in relation to the things in nature, which we regard as

    absolutely, and more than just morally, certain.... Mathematical demonstrations

    have this kind of certainty.... And perhaps even these results of mine will be

    allowed into the class of absolute certainties.... All the other phenomena, or at

    least the general features of the universe and the earth which I have described, can

    hardly be intelligibly explained except in the way I have suggested (1985, 290-

    291).

    Descartes appears to be vacillating in this, the second-to-last paragraph of the Principles 

    and there is no obvious solution to his rhetoric in favor of absolute certainty. While in the

    end he affirms only that the “general features of the universe and earth” are absolutely

    certain, he holds out the possibility that more than this is absolutely certain. Ignoring the

    complication introduced by “absolute certainty”, I propose to understand Descartes as

    claiming that none of his hypotheses are actually “false and uncertain”. In Descartes’

     judgment, not only do they explain the phenomena (something other hypotheses can also

    do), no other hypotheses have the same degree of collective simplicity, intelligibility and

     probability.

    This is an important part of Descartes’ developing view of hypotheses, but the main

    result of my discussion here in section two lies elsewhere. I can summarize what we have

    learned by returning to the complaint of Huygens noted earlier: Descartes’ reference to “grooved

     particles” is a conjecture. In referring to one of Descartes’ analogies and not to one of his

    hypotheses, Huygens is mistaken if he is asserting that Descartes simply offers an analogy

     between visible screws and sub-visible particles without any basis in experience. This is false

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    13/40

     because in the effect of pulling and pushing Descartes clearly registers a specific similarity

    identified through experience. But even if Huygens’ general characterization of the Principles as

    a fiction is correct because, for example, Descartes introduces Stage 2 hypotheses without using

    analogies, there is now at least a question about where precisely we find Descartes engaged in

    idle speculations and arbitrary conjectures. If Descartes’ hypotheses seem to fit this description

    when he introduces them without any evidence save the power of God, what about when analogy

    is used to introduce hypotheses? Are these hypotheses or the analogies themselves arbitrary

    conjectures? In the following sections I try to show that the answer is no.

    III. Descartes’ Scientific Practice

    With the background of the previous section in place, two strategies suggest themselves for

    discussing Descartes’ view of analogy: examining his practice and examining his methodological

    reflections, i.e., his philosophy of analogy. It will not always be easy to pursue these two

    strategies separately from one another, but in this section I focus on Descartes practice, as

    exemplified by work published in the mid-1630s. In the next section I will detail his philosophy

    of analogy. 

    Descartes’ earliest reference to analogy dates from the 1610s. In a notebook preserved by

    Leibniz, Descartes writes that:

    Man has knowledge of natural things only through their resemblance to the things

    which come under the senses. Indeed, our estimate of how much truth a person

    has achieved in his philosophizing will increase the more he has been able to

     propose some similarity between what he is investigating and the things known by

    the senses. (1985, 5)

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    14/40

     

    This is clearly a commitment to analogy and to the epistemological significance of sense

    experience. Already we can see that Descartes believes our knowledge of the natural world

    depends on our ability to find analogies between what the senses reveal and “natural things.”

    These pregnant ideas about the role of analogy and the foundational status of what we

    can observe reach mature expression only in the 1630s.15

     Descartes’ most ambitious and original

    effort in physics, The World, dates from this period. Although it is summarized in Discourse

    Five, where Descartes acknowledges a hypothetical method involving fables and suppositions,

    the hypotheses and analogies that attract the most attention among Descartes’ readers are the

    ones found in the Dioptrics (e.g., Galison 1984; Statile 1999; Garber, Unpublished). It is for this

    reason that I will be concentrate on the Dioptrics, where analogies and the evidence of sense

    experience figure prominently.

    Early in the Dioptrics, Descartes refrains from stating light’s “true nature.” His official

    reason for this modest approach is his narrow interest “to explain how [lights] rays enter into the

    eye, and how they may be deflected by the various bodies they encounter.” As a result, he will

    examine light but he “need not attempt to say what is its true nature.” He continues:

    15 These ideas are also present in the Rules. In Proposition 14 Descartes insists that “… in all

    reasoning it is only by means of comparison [ per comparationem] that we attain an exact

    knowledge of the truth” (1985, p. 57). To which he adds a few lines later “… all knowledge

    whatever – save that which is obtained through simple and pure intuition of a single solitary

    thing – is obtained by means of comparison between two or more things.”

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    15/40

    It will... suffice if I use two or three comparisons [comparaisons] which help to

    conceive light in the way [qui aydent a la conceuior en la façon] that seems most

    suitable for explaining all those of its properties that we know through experience

    and then for deducing all the others that we cannot observe so easily (Descartes

    1985, 152; modified).

    The procedure announced in the Dioptrics involves using analogies to introduce a Stage 2

    hypothesis about light’s nature that will then serve to explain light’s effects. These include the

    transmission of light from a luminous body to our eye – Descartes’ first two analogies deal with

    this effect – and light’s reflection and refraction – Descartes’ third analogy deals with this effect.

    If Descartes’ hypothesis implies these effects, then by his own standard he has a good

    hypothesis.

    At the same time, Descartes’ claim that analogies can be used “to help conceive” his

    hypothesis suggests another measure of a good hypothesis. His phrasing is ambiguous between

    the use of analogy to discover a hypothesis and, having a hypothesis already in hand, the use of

    analogy to make the hypothesis more plausible or easier to accept. Descartes’ practice in the

     Dioptrics shows that he means both. Analogies aid in discovery. They also serve to illustrate

    how hypothesized causes might produce effects, thereby making the hypothesis more plausible.

    It is important to see that this measure of a good hypothesis is independent of what the

    hypothesis allows us to infer about light’s effects. A plausible hypothesis by the “measure of

    analogy” might fail to save the phenomena even though how it would do so, if it could, might be

    easy to understand and fully intelligible because of the wealth of analogies available.

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    16/40

      Writing to Vatier in 1638, Descartes returns to this early passage from the Dioptrics. “As

    for light, if you look at the third page of the Optics, you will see that I have said there expressly

    that I was going to speak about [light] only hypothetically [ par hypothese].” He adds that he

    specifically tried “to convey some idea of [light’s nature] by comparisons [comparaisons]”

    (1991, 87, modified). The rest of Descartes’ letter indicates that the alternative method would

    involve supporting his Stage 2 hypothesis by deducing it from “the first principles of...

    metaphysics” (Ibid., 87). Whereas the Dioptrics gives “a posteriori” proofs, Descartes tells

    Vatier that the alternative to arguing hypothetically is to “prove a priori what I had supposed

    [que i’ai suposé ]” (Ibid., 87; modified). It is interesting that Descartes does not think that he

    would need to change his hypothesis about light if he had followed the alternative method.

    It is time to see how Descartes uses analogy in his practice, in the method he actually

    follows. The first of the three analogies offered in the Dioptrics is the analogy of the blind man’s

    stick. Descartes introduces this analogy by likening the way in which we gain knowledge of the

    world through sight to the way a blind man gains knowledge of his surroundings through the use

    of a stick. “[O]ne might almost say that they see with their hands, or that their stick is the organ

    of some sixth sense given to them in the place of sight” (Ibid., 153). Descartes thinks it equally

    obvious – and presumably a fact we can learn from sense experience – that a blind man’s stick

    gains him knowledge “through the action of these bodies [in the world] when they move against

    his stick, but also through the action of his hand when they do nothing but resist the stick.” In

    other words, in the case of the blind man, having sense experience of the world is the effect of a

    rigid body’s contact with objects in the world.

    “In order to draw a comparison [comparaison] from” the example of the blind man and

    his stick – that is, if we pursue the analogy between sight and touch – we should infer:

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    17/40

     

    light in bodies we call ‘luminous’ to be nothing other than a certain movement, or

    very rapid and lively action, which passes to our eyes through the medium of the

    air and other transparent bodies, just as the movement or resistance of the bodies

    encountered by a blind man passes to his hand by means of his stick. (Ibid., 153)

    In this example of his practice, Descartes uses an analogy to discover an unknown cause.16

     

    The cause is a Stage 2 hypothesis about the nature of light. Although hardly a formal syllogism,

    Descartes follows the above passage by stating that his newly-discovered hypothesis makes the

    instantaneous propagation of light less “strange.” If light is just the motion of a rigid body, like a

    stick, then movement in a luminous body would instantly be felt in the eye.

     Now that we have glimpsed how Descartes uses analogy and sensory knowledge to

    discover a hypothesis, it is worth asking again what precisely the distinction is between an

    analogy and a hypothesis. And what happened to my suggestion in section II that analogies are

    related directly to observation but that hypotheses are not? I believe the answer to these

    questions lies in the fact that Descartes’ Stage 2 hypothesis about light in the Dioptrics itself

     presumes the Stage 1 hypothesis that matter and motion are the defining features of the natural

    world. Every genuine phenomenon must be a manifestation of matter and motion, and this

    includes light. Adopting this Stage 1 hypothesis allows the similarity between a blind man’s use

    16 The ratio-like scheme introduced in the last section can be used to convey Descartes’ first

    analogy. Blind man’s knowledge of the world : Motion by contact between bodies, a stick and

    the blind man’s hand :: Sighted man’s knowledge of the world : Motion between luminous

     bodies, a medium and the sighted man’s eyes.

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    18/40

    of a stick and our use of vision to have the right significance – it enables the analogy to call our

    attention to a subvisible mechanism. This only happens because a further similarity exists

     between the two cases being compared beyond the one Descartes explicitly cites since both must

    work through a species of contact motion. Thus, instead of a self-standing analogy introducing a

    Stage 2 hypothesis, I propose that what is really going on in the  Dioptrics is that Descartes has a

    Stage 1 hypothesis supporting the analogy. The Stage 1 hypothesis and the analogy together lead

    him to his Stage 2 hypothesis.

    If this is right, the answers to the questions asked at the beginning of the last paragraph

    are the following: an analogy is always supported by some hypothesis or other, even when

    analogies are used to discover a hypothesis. Additionally, hypotheses themselves make no direct

    reference to sense experience, but the analogies used to discover them do. And, finally, though

    we will see this more clearly in our analysis of the second analogy from the Dioptrics, an

    analogy makes a hypothesis intelligible by likening it to a familiar and well-understood

    observable phenomenon, such as the contact motion passed through the blind man’s stick.

    Descartes’ second analogy, the vat of wine analogy, enters where the first analogy leaves

    off. In his words, “because our blind man’s stick differs greatly from the air and the other

    transparent bodies through the medium of which we see, I must make use of another comparison

    [comparaison]” (Ibid., 154). Assuming his Stage 2 hypothesis that light is a “movement or very

    rapid and lively action,” Descartes acknowledges here that light travels from a luminous body

    instantly in all directions and it does this without a series of rigid stick-like bodies being present.

    The trouble identified here is conceptual: the medium for light is very different from the

    analogue that aided in the initial discovery of Descartes’ hypothesis. The second analogy

    compares light to the pressure placed on the sides of a vat of wine by the liquid it contains and

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    19/40

    the pieces of grape as they ferment. The vat is supposed to illustrate how the instantaneous

    straight line propagation of light could occur through pressure or “the action or tendency to

    move.” Punch a hole in the bottom of the vat and wine will flow out. Punch another in the side

    and the same will happen. This occurs instantly, according to Descartes, and in spite of the fact

    that the still solid grapes are collected near each of the holes. “In the same way, all the parts of

    the subtle matter in contact with the side of the sun facing us tend in a straight line towards our

    eyes at the very instant they are opened” (Ibid., 154-55). Light, Descartes infers, is a tendency to

    motion, a kind of pressure, that is always present waiting to be felt and, like the wine, it is

    capable of making its way through or around other bodies in its path.

    I claimed earlier that Descartes’ analogies serve both in the discovery of hypotheses and

    in making hypotheses more plausible. Here in the vat of wine analogy, Descartes has shifted to

     plausibility.17

     His Stage 2 hypothesis was discovered using the analogy of the blind man, but the

    first analogy between light and the blind man’s stick is not altogether satisfying. It raises the

     prospect of a significant dissimilarity between the medium through which light travels and the

    medium of the stick such that an accepted fact of light – its instantaneous propagation in a

    straight line and around obstacles – cannot be explained. To handle this dissimilarity Descartes

    needed to show that an asymmetry that is true with respect to the first analogy is not necessarily

    true with respect to the hypothesis about light and other well known phenomena involving

    motion. Thus, the second analogy helps us understand how the Stage 2 hypothesis could still be

    17 Gabbey (1990) maintains that this analogy diverges from the first in that it is only an

    “illustrative analogy” and not a “working model” (p. 277). For more on this point, though put in

    terms of simulation and what simulation can contribute to physics, see Des Chene (2001).

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    20/40

    true even if the analogy used to discover it is not consistent with all of light’s properties or

    effects.18

     

    In the third and most famous of the analogies from the Dioptrics, Descartes compares

    light to a tennis ball or a series of tennis balls. His aim in using this analogy is to illustrate the

    manner in which something like light could produce color, reflect off a surface and refract

    through a medium. Although this analogy holds significant historical interest for its relation to

    Descartes’ convoluted derivation of the sine law of refraction, it follows the pattern set by the

     previous two.19

     Descartes begins by noting an effect of light that is not consistent with the

     previous analogies, both of which presume straight line propagation – when making contact with

    some bodies light “is liable to be deflected by them, or weakened” (Ibid., 155). Next Descartes

    18 The fact that Descartes’ analogies identify distinct effects of the causes he is seeking to

    discover or illustrate has led some to treat his analogies as “models” in the modern sense (e.g.,

    Rodis-Lewis, 1978; Clarke 1982; Gabbey 1990). Such assimilation obscures a serious objection

    to Descartes’ multiple analogies in the Dioptrics. Specifically, if each analogy breaks down in

    some way, then the subvisible world is not identical to any of them. In that case, Descartes does

    not appear to have a Stage 2 hypothesis supported by an analogy but, at best, partial analogies

    supporting a hypothesis. The objection is that any hypothesis can be supported by some

    assembly of partial analogies. (In the next section, we will see that this is very similar to the

    objection Descartes receives from Jean-Baptiste Morin). However, Descartes’ built in constraint

    on acceptable analogies tied to his Stage 1 hypothesis limits which hypothesis can be supported

    even with partial analogies because all the causal analogues must involve matter in motion. I

    discuss this further in the next section.

    19 Schuster (2000) provides a persuasive reconstruction of Descartes’ derivation of the sine law.

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    21/40

     points out that these effects are similar to “the movement of a ball or stone thrown in the air

    [and] deflected by the bodies it encounters.” The ball’s motion is controlled by the laws of

    motion and Descartes infers that light too must “obey the same laws as motion itself.” It may be

    hard to think of the laws of motion as causes but two points are relevant here. First, Descartes

    does in fact think the laws of motion are causes (Ibid., 240). Second, what matters most in the

    analogy is the fact that the behavior of a ball hitting a surface, something knowable through

    sense experience, illustrates how matter in motion can sometimes behave. Light is just one

    species of motion according to Descartes’ Stage 2 hypothesis and his first two analogies, and the

    third analogy simply illustrates that if light is motion it will conform to the laws of motion.

    To sum up, Descartes’ scientific practice shows him using analogies to discover possible

    causes that serve as Stage 2 hypotheses. He also uses analogies to make his hypotheses more

    intelligible or plausible by comparing them to better-understood phenomena. Additionally, we

    saw that when proposing an analogy he seems to proceed with at least one hypothesis in hand,

    the most important being his Stage 1 hypothesis that matter is just extension. In the next section

    we will see how Descartes defends his use of analogy when it is challenged and why he believes

    explanations without analogies cannot be accepted.

    IV. Descartes’ philosophy of analogy

    In discussing Descartes’ analogies thus far, I have maintained that they help to discover or

    illustrate causes of natural phenomena, the effects of which are similar to the effects of a well-

    understood phenomenon of process. Described in this way, there is nothing especially new or

    innovative in Descartes.20

     A comparison is just that, a comparison between two things meant to

    20 To provide a more thorough background for Descartes’ terminology and the models he follows

    or rejects, we would need to investigate, at least, the following: (1) rhetoric, where the trope of

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    22/40

    issue in a plausible conclusion. But Descartes does have a unique philosophy of analogy as part

    of his philosophy of science. This will be the main focus of this section.  

    After the Discourse and its companion Essays are published, Descartes corresponds with

    several hostile critics. Among them is Jean-Baptiste Morin, who questions Descartes’ hypotheses

    as well as his analogies.21

     Taking issue with the significance of analogies generally and the

    specific use Descartes makes of them in supporting his Stage 2 hypothesis about light, Morin

    notes “every comparison [comparaison] is between things that are different; thus according to

    comparatio and the use of exemplum and similitudo abound; (2) logic, where distinctions

     between demonstratio quia, identified as “analysis” or reasoning a posteriori from effects to

    causes, and demonstratio propter quid , identified as “synthesis” or reasoning a priori from

    causes to effects exist; (3) mathematics, where proceeding according to ordo, finding instances

    of ratio, and comparing by means of proportio are features of geometry and algebra; (4)

    astronomy, where the practice of using conjecture and hypothesis to save the phenomena are

    standard fare in dealing with heavenly bodies; (5) medicine, where medical induction and

    semiology make a fine art of observation and inference from effects, understood as signs

    (signum, indica), to hidden causes; (6) theology, where disputes over God’s being, the being of

    his creation, and other characteristics seemingly shared between the two, are conducted in terms

    of comparationes; (7) chemistry, where analogy is a fundamental troupe in explanation; and (8)

    meteorology, where conjecture and unobservable causes fill the Renaissance commentary

    tradition on Aristotle’s Meteorology.

    21 Morin is best remembered for these disputes and for disputes he has with Gassendi, but Morin

    was an important seventeenth-century astrologer and the likely author of the second set of

    objections to Descartes’ Meditations (Garber, 1995).

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    23/40

    you light is not action or motion” (1996, I 543). Yet Morin also recognizes that Descartes wants

    to infer more from his analogies, for he expresses his willingness to “criticize [Descartes’]

    essence or nature of light, which you [Descartes] say is action, or motion, or the inclination to

    motion, or like action or motion, etc. of a subtle matter, etc.” (Ibid., I 547). Morin appears to

     believe Descartes’ analogies evade giving specific details about his “subtle matter” and, in any

    case, the analogies do little to make plausible his Stage 2 hypothesis about the nature of light,

    whether light is action or motion or an inclination to action or motion as the vat of wine analogy

    implies.

    The extent of the disagreement between Descartes and Morin is especially clear where

    Morin objects to Descartes’ explanation of color production with a prism using his Stage 2

    hypothesis and the analogy of spinning balls.22

     In the Meteors, Descartes first recalls his

    description of light from the Dioptrics “as the action or motion of a certain very subtle matter

    whose parts must be imagined as small balls rolling in the pores of earthly matter” (Ibid., VI

    331). Descartes goes on to infer that what diversity we find in light’s effects is not the result of

    the small balls as such but is a product of the way the balls – the material analogue of his “very

    subtle matter” – move (Ibid., VI 333-4). In his own words:

    I understand that these balls can roll in diverse ways according to the diverse

    causes which determine them; and in particular, that all the refractions that occur

    on the same side cause them to turn in the same direction; but when they have no

    neighboring balls that are moved notably faster or slower than they, their turning

    is almost equal to their linear motion; whereas when they have some on one side

    22 For more on color and the rainbow, see Shea (1991) and especially Buchwald (2007).

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    24/40

    that move more slowly, and others on the other side that move as fast or faster, as

    occurs in the confines of shadow and light, then if they meet those that move

    more slowly on the side toward which they are rolling... this causes them to turn

    less quickly than if they were moving in a straight line; and it is just the opposite

    when they encounter them on the other side. (Ibid., VI 331)

    Using his hypothesis about light’s nature and the analogy of spinning balls, Descartes’

    conclusion is that refraction can be understood as a change in the rotational and translational

    motion of subtle matter. Prior to refraction the balls of subtle matter in a beam of light share a

    common translational motion in their direction of propagation. When entering a new medium

    with a refracting surface there is no question of stopping the translational motion, and so long as

    the “neighboring balls” to a given beam of refracted light are moving at the same speed as the

     balls in the beam of light, then refraction will occur without producing color. This is because the

    rotational motion is the same as the motion in the direction of propagation, or as Jed Buchwald

    has put it, “translation couples to rotation in the same way that it does for a ball rolling without

    slipping” (Buchwald 2007, 38). In other words, according to Descartes mere change of direction

    coupled with rotational motion that exactly matches the translational motion will not produce

    color. However, if the “neighboring balls” are moving at different speeds, say because of the

     presence of a shadow, which Descartes identifies with a lack of motion, then the spinning balls

    will spin at different rates in relation to their translational motion.23

     Depending on the motion of

    23 It may be helpful to imagine the observable phenomenon Descartes is appealing to as an

    unequal pinch. On entering a prism subtle matter can be pinched by surrounding matter moving

    at a different speed. Just as pinching a marble with our fingers will cause the marble to spin

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    25/40

    the particles already present in the mediums though which the beam of light travels, the

     periphery of the beam of light will gain or lose speed with any change diminishing toward the

    center of the beam.

    We could go on at some length in analyzing Descartes’ remarks about prisms and

    refraction, but what is most important for us in Descartes’ account is that his analogical

    reasoning leads him to assign the production of color to the variable motion of subtle matter. For

    his part, Morin has considerable difficulty with Descartes’ reference to spinning balls. He cannot

    understand, for example, why Descartes allows balls of the subtle matter to “roll... in air” prior to

    entering a refracting surface even though everything presented in the Meteors concerning

    refraction implied to Morin that the balls begin to spin “only when they encounter a more solid

    [refracting] surface” (1996, I 547). Morin’s failure to appreciate Descartes’ use of analogy as

    well as Descartes’ unwillingness to abandon analogies characterizes the rest of the

    correspondence between the two.

    Descartes’ initially defends himself in a letter sent five months after Morin’s initial

    correspondence. First Descartes describes a broad-minded conception of analogy:

    you have wonderfully shrunk the meaning of the word ‘like’… and you would

    like for it to be used only to join the terms of a comparison [comparaison], which

    is between different things. But if this were true, then when one said that

    someone did something like a learned person, then that would mean that he

    wasn’t learned. (Ibid., II 204-5)

     because of the unequal force that we apply, refracting light can be pinched by “neighboring

     balls”. 

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    26/40

     

    There is no doubt that Morin commits himself to an impoverished view of analogy and Descartes

    is right to reject Morin’s proposal. Nevertheless, the context of Morin’s remarks is the discovery

    of Descartes’ Stage 2 hypothesis about light and the subsequent analogies used to illustrate

    light’s effects in keeping with the initial hypothesis. Just as Descartes advances his position in

    the Dioptrics by hypothesis and analogy, however, his defense of the Meteors uses the same

    strategy:

    I do not speak at all about the subtle matter, but about wood balls, or other visible

    matter [matiere visible], which are pushed towards water; as is evident from my

    making them turn completely contrary to the parts of the subtle matter, and

    compare [compare] the turning which they acquire in leaving air and entering

    water, to that which the parts of the subtle matter acquire in leaving water or glass

    and entering air. (Ibid., II 208)

    This is the first mention of “wood balls” in Descartes’ discussion of light but the point he is

    trying to make is clear enough. In the Meteors he uses an analogy to illustrate how his Stage 2 

    hypotheis about light might explain the production of color. This is how Morin should

    understand the claim from the Meteors that light’s action “must be imagined” in terms of

    spinning balls. Put another way, Descartes is telling Morin that the majority of the discussion in

    the Meteors concerns the Known Effect1 : Known Cause of spinning balls, and Morin has taken

    the analogy too literally.

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    27/40

      Morin is no more convinced by this new analogy than he had been by the Meteors. The

    tone of Morin’s reply one month later even has an air of exasperation. He was simply unwilling

    to allow analogies with observable phenomena to guide a discussion about the nature of light and

    the manner in which it produced its effects. As he writes, “difficulties in physics are rarely put to

    rest by comparisons; there is nearly always some difference, or some ambiguity, or the

    [substitution of] the obscure by the more obscure” (Ibid., II 291). Morin reiterates the difficulties

    he finds in Descartes’ appeal to analogy later in the same letter. Given that “you [Descartes]

    respond only through comparisons [comparaisons], I have already warned you that

    [comparisons] rarely are appropriate for resolving a difficulty” (Ibid., II 297). And so, Morin

    ignores Descartes’ new analogy of spinning wooden balls and askes again about the subtle matter

    that continued to elude him.

    To the modern reader Morin may appear to have the better argument. After all, part of the

    reason we turn to analogy is because we cannot provide deductive arguments. This bias against

    analogical reasoning can be traced to the Ancient world and is manifest in Aristotle and the

    commentary tradition on the Posterior Analytics (Allen 2001). Descartes’ own vacillation over

    the truth of his hypotheses, coupled with his insistence that he could provide a demonstration if

    he wanted to, looks to be further evidence that analogical reasoning is a second-rate option even

    for him. Thus, we might hear Morin as saying: if you can demonstrate these claims demonstrate

    them, do not give us partial analogies that must be abandoned whenever a question arises about

    the subtle matter that is the effect’s true cause. In other words, explain the nature of light and its

    effects without analogies or accept that you have no coherent view of the nature of light.

    Using comparisons to make claims specifically about the natural world was not new to

    Descartes. At least since Epicurus, whose letter to Herodotus was again available in the late

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    28/40

    sixteenth century atomists had been arguing for the existence of the subvisible void by drawing a

    comparison to the motion of observable objects into empty space. Gassendi commented

    explicitly on Epicurus’ letter and showed considerable interest in analogical reasoning himself

    (e.g., 1981 [1658], p. 160; 1684, 14). Descartes also refers to the atomists’ use of analogical

    reasoning near the end of the Principles (1996, VIII 325). Yet, he does not refer to the precedent

    from atomists in response to Morin. Instead, in his next letter Descartes concedes the point that

    he uses analogy to answer difficult questions in physics and then offers a theory of falsification,

    or what I have been calling his “philosophy of analogy”:

    True, the comparisons [comparaisons] that are usually employed in the Schools

    explain intellectual matters by means of physical ones, substances by means of

    accidents, or at any rate, one quality by means of a quality of a different kind, and

    they are not very instructive [n’instruisent que fort peu]. But in the comparisons

    [ pource qu’en celles] which I employ, I compare motions only with other

    motions, or shapes with other shapes; that is, I compare things that are too small

    to be perceived by the senses with other things that can be so perceived, the latter

    differing from the former simply as a large circle differs from a small one. I

    maintain, therefore, that comparisons of this sort are the most appropriate means

    [ells sont le moyen le plus propre] available to the human mind for laying bare the

    truth in problems of physics [questions Physiques]. I would go so far as to say

    that, when someone makes an assertion concerning nature which cannot be

    explained by any such comparison [qui ne peut ester expliquée par aucune telle

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    29/40

    comparaison], I think I have demonstrative knowledge that the point is false [ je

     pense sçauoir par demonstration qu’elle est fausse]. (1991, 122)

    There are two distinct claims being made here. One is a defense of his earlier practice. The other

    is a new claim, consistent with his earlier practice, but of considerable interest in its own right. In

    the remainder of this section I will first discuss Descartes’ defense and then his philosophy of

    analogy.

    Whereas the scholastics “explain intellectual matters by means of physical ones,

    substances by means of accidents, or at any rate, one quality by means of a quality of a different

    kind”, Descartes’ analogies can inform us about the world “too small to be perceived.” More

    than this even, and against Morin’s position, analogies are the “most appropriate” means for

    supporting or making a claim in physics.24

     Unlike the scholastic’s analogies, as Descartes

    describes them, which commit what we would now call a “category mistake,” Descartes’

    analogies are informative and relevant because they confine themselves to the same ontological

    category. Descartes clearly believes this last constraint precludes comparisons like those offered

     by scholastics, but it is worth noting that without an additional premise this is not so. Seeing

    what this premise is is not easy, however, because Descartes does not specify which specific

    analogies he finds objectionable.

    Consider, however, a passage from the Rules, where Descartes distinguishes his use of a

     particular analogy:

    24 In a contemporaneous letter, Descartes writes to Plempius that it “is perfectly reasonable to

     judge of things which are too small for the senses to perceive by the example and similarity of

    those we see” (1991, p. 65; modified).

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    30/40

     

    Let us then conceive of the matter in the following way. First, in so far as our

    external senses are all parts of the body, sense-perception... is merely passive...

    sense-perception occurs in the same way in which wax takes on an impression

    from a seal. It should not be thought that I have a mere analogy [analogiam] in

    mind here: we must think of the external shape of the sentient body as being

    really changed by the object in exactly the same way as the shape of the surface of

    the wax is altered by the seal. (1985, 40)

    In the Rules, Descartes is rejecting the scholastic description of how sense-perception takes

     place. I think it is plausible to believe that Descartes has the scholastics in mind as the ones who

    use the example of the wax and seal as a “mere analogy [analogiam].” Yet, they could

    legitimately use the comparison of wax receiving a seal without violating Descartes’ stipulation

    that we only use analogies within the same ontological category. For the scholastic, both sense-

     perception and the wax and seal involve the transfer of form from an object impressing itself

    upon formable matter. In slightly more technical terms, for the scholastic the perception to be

    explained and the transfer of a “real quality” from the object both belong to the category of

    quality. The same goes for the seal and wax. Thus, by the scholastic’s lights, comparing the two

    satisfies Descartes’ strict standard for a good analogy: avoid category mistakes.

    Descartes understands his ontological constraint as limiting comparisons to “things that

    are too small to be perceived by the senses with other things that can be so perceived, the latter

    differing from the former simply as a large circle differs from a small one.” But how does

    Descartes know that things too small to be perceived do not differ in kind from sensible objects?

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    31/40

    This question brings us back again to Descartes’ Stage 1 hypothesis and the additional premise

    that rules out the scholastic’s use of the seal and wax analogy. What is unstated in the letter to

    Morin, just as it was unstated in the Dioptrics as we saw in the last section, is Descartes’

    conception of matter as extension.

    The analogy Descartes draws between his activity in physics and the geometer’s work

    with circles brings out nicely the role played by his Stage 1 hypothesis. A circle, whether large

    or small, may be defined as a figure generated by describing all points equidistant from a given

    center. This is what it is to be a circle and even if particular circles will vary in their accidents of

    color or size, they remain essentially the same. From their definition, further truths can be known

    to apply to circles, such as the fact that each circle’s radius is half its diameter or that π is equal

    to every circle’s circumference divided by its diameter. In the latter case, geometers can

    legitimately compare a large circle to a small circle by comparing the circumference divided by

    the diameter of the one to the circumference divided by the diameter of the other to find an

    unknown quantity. Put into a ratio-like form where the unknown quantity is a diameter of one of

    the circles we get:

    Known Circumferance1 : Known Diameter 1 :: Known Circumferance2 : Unknown

    Diameter.

    This is a legitimate comparison given the essential similarity of all circles. When Descartes uses

    analogies that belong to the same ontological category, his Stage 1 hypothesis his hypothesis

    serves exactly the same role as the definition of the circle for the geometer. Recall the ration-like

    form of Descartes’ analogies:

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    32/40

     

    Known Effect1 : Known Cause :: Known Effect2 : Unknown Cause.

    Descartes’ analogies are informative and legitimate because they are limited to the same

    ontological category where everything is essentially the same – the physicist is just dealing with

    matter in motion.25

      The difficulty the scholastic encounters is that he has too many ontological

    categories informing his analogies.

    Besides clarifying his use of analogy to Morin and the role played by his Stage 1

    hypotheis, Descartes also says that analogies are a necessary part of physics. Lacking an analogy

    of the sort he advocates, Descartes claims that we have definitive reason to believe a proposed

    explanation is false; i.e., the effect or the cause is either non-existent or outside of nature. This

    suggestion is unacceptable to Morin and his very deep disagreement is evident in the last letter

     between the two:

    I am amazed that you think so highly of comparisons to prove things in physics,

    to the point of saying that ‘when someone makes an assertion concerning nature

    which cannot be explained by any such analogy, I think I have demonstrative

    knowledge that the point is false,’ since one can find many effects in nature which

    have nothing resembling them. (1996, II 411; emphasis added).

    25 This also helps explain why Descartes nowhere shows any hesitance about problems generated

     by scale-variance. The laws of nature are scale-invariant because they owe the existence to

    God’s immutability and the nature of his creation, namely extension. There is no more scale-

    variance in a physics of extension as there is in a geometry of extension.  

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    33/40

     

    As before, Morin has a point. It is one thing to use an analogy to aid in discovery or to make a

    hypothesis more intelligible, but something else entirely to claim that analogies between motions

    or analogies between shapes are the only acceptable way to use analogies in physics. It is

    something even more to say that without an analogy an explanation is lacking.

    Again, what Morin does not appreciate is Descartes’ Stage 1 hypothesis that all matter is

     just extension. This point is made in Garber (Unpublished) and it is the assumption about

    matter’s essence that makes all the difference to Descartes’ philosophy of analogy.26

     For

    Descartes’ view is not simply, where there is a cause there is an analogy. Rather, his view is that

    where there is just extension there will always be some analogy to aid in discovery or

    illustration. And, of course, by a Stage 1 hypothesis extension is everywhere. Descartes makes

    this explicit in the Principles:

    I... acknowledge that I recognize no matter in corporeal things apart from that

    which the geometers call quantity... i.e. that to which every kind of division,

    shape and motion is applicable. Moreover, my consideration of such matter

    involves absolutely nothing apart from these divisions, shapes and motions….

    And since all natural phenomena can be explained in this way... I do not think that

    any other principles are either admissible or desirable in physics. (1985, 247).

    26 An alternative assumption is Descartes’ commitment to a unified science (Statile, 1999). Yet a

    third alternative, though it is not Descartes’ own, is simplicity. I discuss simplicity in the

    conclusion below.

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    34/40

    If something is entirely unlike shape, size or motion, it will not enter into Descartes’ physics.27

     

    Whereas Morin, like the scholastics, accepts a plurality of ontological categories, Descartes does

    not. For him, explanations without analogy run afoul of an immediate consequence of his

    ontology.

    Thus, Descartes’ method in physics looks something like this: we know the general

     principles that define the material world; e.g. matter is just extension, there are certain laws of

    nature. We observe a given effect. To explain what we observe we need to proceed to the sub-

    visible world. This world cannot be observed. Given my principles, however, the subvisible

    world is essentially the material world I sense, but on a much smaller scale. To explain what we

    observe we should look for some combination of sizes, shapes and motions of sensible bodies

    that produce effects similar to the ones we are looking to explain. Once we find such a

    combination, we have an analogy with one missing term. We next infer the missing term, the

    Unknown Cause, on the basis of the observable analogue – Known Effect1: Known Cause. Or,

    as Descartes himself puts it in the Principles: “Later on, when I observed just such effects in

    objects that can be perceived by the senses, I judged that they in fact arose from just such an

    interaction of bodies that cannot be perceived – especially since it seemed impossible to think up

    any other explanation for them” (Ibid., 288). The procedure Descartes advocates requires us to

    find analogues whose behavior mimics the behavior that we are trying to explain. Only then can

    we infer to the extended causes we cannot see.

    V Conclusion

    27 This claim must be modified slightly due to the presence of mind-body unions, whose sensory

    states are studied, at least partially, by the physicist. For more on this qualification see Hatfield

    2000.

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    35/40

    In this paper, I have sought to elucidate Descartes’ use of analogy, and in particular to show how

    we should understand the differences between the roles of analogies and hypotheses in his

     physics. I also claimed that Descartes’ view holds considerable appeal. But given how

    frequently his Stage 1 hypothesis about the essence of matter entered into the last two sections,

    this may seem a bizarre claim. For how can Descartes’ philosophy of analogy look appealing

    unless we accept his Stage 1 hypothesis? A response can be found in the value we assign to

    simplicity when choosing among competing theories and explanations. Descartes promotes

    simplicity in physics by embracing his Stage 1 hypothesis that matter is extension. As we have

    seen, this is the fundamental principle of his physics and it is this principle that allows him to

    reject explanations for which an analogy cannot be given. In hindsight, Descartes’ physics gains

    its simplicity at the cost of embracing a dubiously austere ontology. If we are willing to see

    Descartes’ claims to Morin as part of an effort to insist that we preserve simplicity, however, the

    absence of an analogy may just be a sign that simplicity, at the level of our fundamental

     principles, is being compromised.28

     Should we accept an explanation to which no analogy

    applies and add complexity to our principles? This is the question Descartes’ philosophy of

    analogy and its theory of falsification is asking. His answer was an emphatic no -- too emphatic

     because of how conservative such a strong emphasis on simplicity turns out to be – but

    28 Only after reading Bartha (2010) was this point clear to me. Bartha gives what he calls a “top-

    down justification” of analogical reasoning that derives, in part, from the way analogies promote

    simplicity (chapter 7). Although Bartha maintains unity is the most important value to promote

    and specifically rejects accounts that emphasize only simplicity, applied to falsification what I

    am about to say about Descartes may be read as a much abbreviated version of Bartha’s top-

    down justification where the lack of analogy makes a proposed explanation implausible.

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    36/40

    Descartes’ question is one we all face regardless of what our fundamental principles turn out to

     be. To accept that no analogies exist is to accept Morin’s belief that “one can find many effects

    in nature which have nothing resembling them.” Even today there are very few of these. 

    Acknowledgments

    Redacted for blind review

    References

    Allen, J. (2001). Inference from Signs: Ancient Debates About The Nature of Evidence. Oxford:

    Clarendon Press.

    Anstey, P. (2005). Experimental versus Speculative Natural Philosophy. In P. Anstey & J.

    Shuster  (Eds.), The Science of Nature in the Seventeenth Century: Patters of Change in

     Early Modern Natural Philosophy (pp. 215-242). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Ariew, R. (2010). The New Matter Theory and Its Epistemology: Descartes (and late

    Scholastics) on Hypotheses and Moral Certainty. In P. Anstey & D. Jalobeanu (Eds.),

    Vanishing Matter and the Laws of Motion: Descartes and Beyond  (pp. 31-48). London:

    Routledge.

    Bartha, P. (2010). By Parallel Reasoning: The Construction and evaluation of Analogical

     Arguments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Bellis, D. (2010). Le visible et l’invisible dans la pensée Cartésienne: Figuration, imagination et

    vision dans la philosophie naturelle de René Descartes (2 vols., PhD diss.). Université

    Paris-Sorbonne. 

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    37/40

    Buchwald, J. (2007). Descartes’s Experimental Journey Past the Prism and Through the Invisible

    World to the Rainbow. Annals of Science, 65, 1-46.

    Clarke, D. (1982). Descartes’ philosophy of science. University Park: Penn State University

    Press.

    Clarke, D. (1989). Occult Powers and Qualities: Cartesian Natural Philosophy Under Louis

     XVth. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Clarke, D. (1990). The Discours and Hypotheses. In G. Belgioioso, G. Cimino, P. Costabel, & G.

    Papuli (Eds.), Descartes: Il Methodo E I Saggi (pp. 201-209). Rome: Enciclopedia

    Italiana,.

    Clarke, D. (2010). Hypotheses. In D. Clarke and C. Wilson  (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of

    Philosophy in Early Modern Europe (pp. 249-271). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Descartes, R. (1985). The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, (J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff &

    D. Murdoch, Eds.) (Vol. 2). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Descartes, R. (1991). The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, (J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, D.

    Murdoch, & A. Kenny, Eds.) (Vol. 3). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Descartes, R. (1996). Oeuvres de Descartes (C. Adam & P. Tannery, Eds.) (11 vols.). Paris: J.

    Vrin.

    Des Chene, D. (2001). Spirits and Clocks: Machine and Organism in Descartes. Ithaca: Cornell

    University Press.

    Gabbey, A. (1990). Explanatory Structures and Models in Descartes’ Physics. In G. Belgioioso,

    G. Cimino, P. Costabel, & G. Papuli (Eds.), Descartes: Il Methodo E I Saggi (pp. 273-

    286). Rome: Enciclopedia Italiana.

    Galison, P. (1984). Descartes’s Comparisons. Isis 75, 311-326.

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    38/40

    Garber, D. (1978). Science and Certainty in Descartes. In M. Hooker  (Ed.), Descartes: Critical

    and Interpretative Essays (pp. 114-151). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press.

    Garber, D. (1995). J.-B. Morin and the Second Objections. In R. Ariew & M. Grene (Eds.),

     Descartes and His Contemporaries: Meditations, Objections and Replies (pp. 63-82).

    Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Garber, D. (Unpublished). Early Modern Analogies and Models: Descartes and Galileo.

    Gassendi, P. (1981). Pierre Gassendi’s Institutio Logica (H. Jones, Trans.). Assen: Van Gorcum.

    (First published 1658)

    Gassendi, P. (1684). Syntagma Philosophiae Epicuri cum Refutationibus Dogmatum.

    Amsterdam: Janssonio-Waesbergios.

    Hatfield, G. (1988). Science, Certainty, and Descartes. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial

     Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 2, 249-262.

    Hatfield, G. (2000). Descartes naturalism about the mental. In S. Gaukroger, J. Schuster & J.

    Sutton (Eds.), Descartes’ Natural Philosophy (pp. 630-658). London: Routledge.

    Hesse, M. (1966). Models and Analogies in Science. South Bend: University of Notre Dame

    Press.

    Huygens, C. (1888-1950). Œuvrées Complete de Huygens (J. A. Vollgraff, Ed.) (22 vols.). The

    Hague: N. Nihoff.

    Lauden, L. (1966). The Clock Metaphor and Probabilism: The Impact of Descartes on English

    Methodological Thought, 1650-1665. Annals of Science, 22, 73-104.

    Lüthy, C. (2006). Where Logical Necessity Becomes Visual Persuasion: Descartes’s Clear and

    Distinct Illustrations. In S. Kusukawa & I. Maclean (Eds.), Transmitting Knowledge:

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    39/40

    Words, Images, And Instruments in Early Modern Europe (pp. 97-137). Oxford: Oxford

    University Press.

    Martin, C. (2011). Renaissance Meteorology from Pompanazzi to Descartes. Baltimore: Johns

    Hopkins University Press. 

    McMullin, E. (2008). Explanation as Confirmation in Descartes’ Natural Philosophy. In J.

    Broughton & J. Carriero (Eds.), A Companion to Descartes (pp.84-102). Oxford:

    Blackwell Publishing.

    McMullin, E. (2009). Hypothesis in Early Modern Science. In M. Heidelberger & G. Schiemann  

    (Eds.), The Significance of the Hypothetical in the Natural Sciences (pp. 7-37). New

    York: Walter de Gruyter . 

     Newton, I. (1999). The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy (I. B. Cohen

    & A. Whitman, Trans.). Berkeley: University of California Press. (First Published 1687)

    Palmerina, C. R. (2007). Bodies in Water Like Planets in the Skies: Uses and Abuses of

    Analogical Reasoning in the Study of Planetary Motion. In M. Camerota, M. Bucciantini,

    & S. Roux  (Eds.), Mechanics and Cosmology in the Medieval and Early Modern Period ,

    (pp. 145–168). Florence: Olschki.

    Sakelleriadis, S. (1982). Descartes’ use of empirical data to test hypotheses. Isis, 73, 68-76.

    Sabra, A. I. (1967). Theories of Light: from Descartes to Newton. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press.

    Schuster, J. 2000. Descartes opticien: the construction f the law of refraction and the

    manufacture of its physical rationales, 1618-29. In S. Gaukroger, J. Schuster & J. Sutton 

    (Eds.), Descartes’ Natural Philosophy (pp. 258-312). London: Routledge.

  • 8/18/2019 Solo Mirar La Bibliografia

    40/40

    Shea, W. R. (1991). The Magic of Numbers and Motion: The Scientific Career of René

     Descartes. Canton: Science History Publications.

    Statile, G. (1999). The necessity of analogy in Cartesian science. The Philosophical Forum,

    XXX, 217-232.